Probably, if you were going to read it you have already, but if you haven't ... you might want to pick it up. It was the #1 New York Times Bestseller in 2006 and it's still quite relevant today -- maybe more so, who knows.
Normally we may think of evolution as a drive toward complexity, but bacteria has gone the other direction, it's evolved downward into simplicity and into very niche environments. This is an excellent survival strategy - what will survive any catastrophe you can imagine? Somewhere, bacteria, probably.
But most animals have opted for complexity and flexibility instead. They are able to move about and adapt to new environments. But here's the rub: since they choose to be flexible, they have to be flexible.
There is a direct analogy in the gastronomic world, it turns out. Some creatures have taken the simple approach by consuming a limited range of things. They can afford to do this because they have evolved elaborate intestines with which to work food over thoroughly and in which to harbor bacteria which converts one sort of input into all the various nutrients their bodies need. These are the herbivores and carnivores, and genetic code alone, which we call instinct, is sufficient to get them fed.
On the other hand, omnivores have taken the high road; their innards are leaner and less elaborate so they must gather the right mix of inputs themselves. And in doing so, they must avoid the dangerous ones. This requires a lot of care, and thought, and therefore ... big brains. It's a tradeoff of a simple lifestyle and an elaborate belly, or a complicated lifestyle, and a lean interior. So the omnivore's dilemma is gathering how to gather the right foods and not take in the harmful kind. That in itself is a dilemma, but Pollan points out there are plenty of moral quandries as well.
The book is as entertaining as The Botany of Desire (2001), in which he looked at the story of apples, potatos, tulips, and marijuana from the plants' perspective. Here he takes on corn, grass, meat, and fungus, and once again we benefit from his careful research and introspection (the latter, occasionally laid on a little thick, for my taste). He also does a great deal of field observation, visiting the food factories and farms, talking to many different kinds of people, gathering mushrooms, and even slitting some chicken necks himself, and shooting a wild boar. He describes much of this so well I felt I had done it too.
His best field trips included a large sustainable farm in Virginia where production is high, costs are relatively low, waste is almost nil, and the animals are mostly content. It's most impressive in the cleverness with which it all works, and the owner explains that in detail. It's a stark contrast to some of the more corporate operations - like a standard corn-fed feedlot, a poultry farm, even an organic farm that turned out to be pretty much like the others. In these chapters the moral dilemmas come into the sharpest focus.
Food -- if you haven't noticed -- has become a new moral battleground, and when Pollan disparaged the new methods, and the lower quality of food they sometimes produce at times I felt he didn't fully appreciate the countervailing moral implications of the much larger quantities turned out now.
All that food is a good thing, too. When he marveled that corn production increased from 75 bu/acre in 1950 to 180 in 2006 (140% increase, and often to the detriment of small time farmers), he didn't mention that world population increased by 172% in the same period. Sometimes I though it was a little one-sided because the older methods could not easily produce the food we need now. Hybrid vigor, that gives us pumped up ears of corn, is itself infertile. That's not a Monsanto conspiracy -- as he intimates -- it is a fact of nature. Vigorous hybrids, like mules, are often -- oddly -- infertile. In the end it appears he was sometimes just exploring some of the more extreme views of his interviewees, as his own conclusions seemed balanced and reasonable, in my opinion. As a reader I felt I had been treated fairly.
First, it's corn's dizzying ascendency as a food source, with the field trip to a chemical plant that rips the kernal pulp apart, sending it out in a tangle of different spigots -- some headed for the gas tank, others to the various mixers of myriad foodstuffs, others to make non-edibles. There's a good discussion of the political and economic forces driving the corn industry too. In the second section, on "grass," he works on a the sustainable Virginia farm, among other things. When it comes to meat, he compares the sustainable approach to that in a large organic poultry operation, a feedlot, and commercial slaughterhouse, and more. And all through the book he comments on underlying philosophical issues.
And the section of fungus (mushrooms) is interesting from a botanical perspective, mostly. It could have been in The Botany of Desire. In the end he pulls the story together by describing his "perfect meal" made up of perfect ingredients, served to perfect guests. That just seemed unnecessary, to me but by that time I'd had a good enough intellectual and philosophical material to chew on - enough food for thought, you might say - to forgive him a little retrospective self-indulgence.
Tuesday, May 29, 2012
Saturday, May 12, 2012
Thinking, Fast and Slow (a review)
Kahneman, it turns out, is a Nobel laureate for developing prospect theory, and he has been actively working in the field for nearly 60 years. The Theory (with lifelong collaborator Amos Tversky) suggests that people evaluate risks on the basis of losses and gains from a reference point, and not simply on outcomes, as utility theory would suggest.
The book is a summary of his and others' research on judgments and decisions. He started his own work at 20 when he was asked to determine which prospective officers in the Israeli Army should be promoted. His PhD is from Berkeley and he’s now faculty emeritus at Princeton. He is collaborative, and ingenious, and focused on ways in which the human mind cuts corners and what can be done about it. At the end of each chapter he suggests how lessons from these often startling findings can be used in daily life, to think more clearly. So here is the main point. In ways we can understand and predict, we make systematic errors in judgment throughout the day. It’s probably because of natural selection that we’re good at making quick decisions and, although they are often good enough, they are also rife with shortcuts, exaggerations and mistakes. Then they are capped off neatly with overconfidence.
He says the mind has two operating systems which he labels 1
and 2. The first is the intuitive mind,
the transparent bit that recognizes a pencil as a pencil, or a face as angry or
sad. It's the part that chooses between fight and flight, that judges the size of numbers, keeps track of time, recalls
memories, and basically takes the first quick swing at everything. We consider this “knowing.” System 2, what you
might call “thinking,” includes estimation, calculation, and all manner of
figuring out – much of which happens very fast and we are at least
partially aware when it's at work. Both systems cut
corners, jump to conclusions, omit inconvenient information, exaggerate, and
guess. System 2’s biggest problem,
according to Kahneman, is laziness. It
leaves System 1 in charge, and when called on it does the minimum
that is required. Generally this means piecing
together a credible solution, then going back to rest.
At first this dichotomy seemed a bit forced to me, as I
thought there must be a continuum instead. But it turned out to be a fabulous
way to parse out how, when, and why our thinking can go wrong.
Things we encounter first hand seem more important and more
common than they should, as do things we can easily recall. When the chance of something (good or bad) is
small we tend to either ignore or exaggerate the possibility of it happening. We consider losses about twice as
important as an equal gain. Thoughts immediately
preceding can dramatically influence a judgment. In retrospect, assessing an event, we give far
too little weight to blind luck. Considering
options separately often results in different conclusions than what you would arrive at with a broader framework. We use stereotypes to
draw inferences from the group to the individual, and the other way
around. And we’re bad at statistics. Consider this:
A woman is seen reading the New York Times on the New York subway. Which of the following is a better bet about her level of education?
-
She has a PhD
- She does not have a college degree
If you chose the first, as I did, think again. There are a lot more nongraduates than PhDs
riding the subway. We overlooked the base
data.
Here’s a clever one:
Hearing that the highest incidences of kidney cancer in U.S. counties are found in the rural, sparsely populated states you might guess the reason: these places are poorer, less educated, with less access to health care, where people have high-fat diets, drink more and smoke. That would certainly make some sense. It’s a coherent, compelling, and completely fabricated story.
If you had heard instead that these same areas have the lowest rates of kidney cancer, you might come up with this one: rural living is healthier, with clean air, fresh locally grown food, people get more exercise and suffer less stress than they would in urban areas.
So which of these two statements about kidney cancer is true? Both are true; you see, there are fewer people in
rural counties, and we are comparing cases per 1,000, and wher the denominator
is small random variations in the numerator
will cause large changes in the rate.
Example: If a disease affects 20% of the greater population, in counties
with just 2 people the rate is likely to be 0%, some will have 50%, and a few 100%.
None will reflect the actual average. This is a statistical
phenomenon which even statisticians often overlook.
Some of the findings in the book as so bizarre I still have
my doubts, although the research seems sound, has been replicated, results
are consistent, and the effects are strong.
For example, when subjects were asked to estimate the percentage of
African nations which are members of the UN it mattered whether the respondents
had just spun a 10 or 65 on a (rigged) “random” wheel. Their estimates for UN membership averaged
25% and 45%, respectively! While people
are holding a sequence of numbers in their head they have less self-control
eating cake! Or if they grip a pencil between
their teeth (forcing a smile) cartoons seem funnier to them compared to when they hold
it between pursed lips (forcing a frown)!
People pencil-frowning will concentrate more strongly on the task at
hand. And those required to nod were more likely to
agree with an editorial they listen to than those who were told to shake their
heads. These results just seems
absurd. I admit that my incredulity is not evidence that it's not true. I just don't see how such simplistic influences would not be exploited, and therefore removed, by evolutionary forces. However, I found myself falling for many of the little test-yourself demonstrations in the book. Consider this question:
Was Ghandi
130 years old when he died? You’ll know
he wasn’t. But how old was he, when he
died? The typical response is
significantly a larger number, compared to subjects who were first asked if he
had died at the age of 40. The first
group would tend to adjust from 130 downward until they hit ages they thought
were plausible; and the others do the same upward from 40. Someone who figured Ghandi was between 65 and
85 might guess nearly a 20 year difference, depending only on the anchor they
had been primed with.
Anchors
are one of many subtle influences to bias our thinking. Here are
some others:
The availability heuristic (page 129), confidence by coherence
(209), the illusion of validity (211), the illusion of skill (212), the illusion of
intuition/ strength of algorithms (223) , the hindsight bias (202), the
illusion of control (259), the halo effect (199), nonregression to the mean (175), inside vs. outside view (248), the planning
fallacy (250), stereotyping (168) , representativeness (149), the substitution effect
(139), probability neglect (144), statistical and causal base rates (168), the conjunction
fallacy (158), theory induced blindness (277), risk aversion (270), loss aversion (284), the endowment effect (293),
bad news bias (301), possibility effect (311), certainty effect (311), the expectation
principle (312), denominator neglect (329), and overweighting (333). There is narrow vs. broad framing (336), reference
points (281), the sunk cost fallacy (345), and the evaluability hypothesis
(360), and the effect of categories (356).
The focusing illusion (402) is a simple one, with reach: (“nothing in
life is as important as you think it is when you are thinking about it”), as is
WYSIATI (153: “what you see is all there is”).
This may seem like a chore to work through, but it’s
not. The writing is very clear and
engaging, and the 38 well-crafted chapters are each, remarkably, 10 pages
long. The book has plenty of examples, end notes with references,
concluding advice, full reprints of two seminal journal articles in two appendices, and lots of little
demonstrations you can try on yourself.
Another example of these. Which of
these two opportunities would you prefer?:
- a gamble that offers a 10% chance to win $95 and 90% chance to lose $5
- or would you pay $5 for a 10% chance to win $100 and a 90% chance to win nothing?
Most people find the second one more attractive. The fact that they are identical
is difficult to see because we are more adverse to losing $5 than we are to paying
$5. Here’s another: You are considering
surgery (with slightly better long-term results than radiation therapy) and you
were told, about the surgery
- The one-month survival rate is 90%
- There is a 10% mortality in the first month.
- Adam switches from a gas-guzzler of 12 mpg to a slightly less voracious guzzler: 14 mpg
- Beth switches from a 30 mpg car to one that runs at 40 mpg
Who will save more gas by switching? The answer is Adam, by a large margin.
One of the best sections of the book is the last. It
describes two very distinct senses of self: one is the experiencing self and the other,
the remembering self. When someone asks “how
are you?” it might mean "how's your mood right now?" but more likely "how have things been going?” … in other words ... “how happy are you with your
memories?” It’s the remembering self
that most people care about, whether they're looking at their own lives (it’s why we take pictures on vacations) or others'. When subjects were asked to imagine taking a dream vacation, after which all memory of it would be erased,
most would not send themselves (or another amnesic)
to hike mountains or trek through the jungle. "These experiences are
mostly painful in real time and gain value from the expectation that both the
pain and the joy of reaching the goal will be memorable.” “Odd as it may seem,” Kahneman concludes, “I am my
remembering self, and the experiencing self, who does my living, is like a
stranger to me.”
Unfortunately it's a little worse still, because the
remembering self doesn’t represent the experiencing self very accurately. Looking
back, durations of experiences don't matter much. Only two things do: 1. peaks (good or bad), and 2. how the event ended. Kahneman explains how these findings can be put to practical use, and also how education, religion,
illness, poverty, wealth, and other factors impact the two forms of satisfaction.
It’s a great book -- I believe it's a full life’s work -- and my criticisms are minor. Maybe not enough distinction was
made between one-time judgments and iterated ones. In the Prisoner’s Dilemma, for example,
once-off games lead to mutual defection but when done repeatedly with the same
players (as in the real world) it leads instead to altruism. Some of the results in a psychology lab may be quite different in the real world.
There are also a few surprising typos, like a mix-up on page 335,
where “AD” and “BC” are switched, throwing off the explanation; and on page 337
two miscalculations in the formulas actually invalidate the results.
But if these are the low points, they are not very low. The peaks were many and very high -- and even though it took me almost a month to read, but duration doesn't count for much -- I'm remember it very fondly and it will sit on my top shelf. Next to Pinker.
(Ghandi died at 79, BTW)
(Ghandi died at 79, BTW)
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)